442 lines
22 KiB
Markdown
442 lines
22 KiB
Markdown
---
|
||
title: "Informal definitions of key concepts in propositional logic"
|
||
slug: /informal-concepts-propositional-logic/
|
||
date: 2021-11-27
|
||
tags: ["article"]
|
||
---
|
||
|
||
## Introduction
|
||
|
||
This post is the first of a series on propositional logic that introduces the
|
||
foundational logical concepts of validity, soundness, truth, falsity,
|
||
possibility and indeterminacy. These concepts are defined here informally and
|
||
will receive formal articulation in later posts.
|
||
|
||
## What is propositional logic?
|
||
|
||
The chief unit of propositional logic is the _proposition_. It is typically said
|
||
that the sentences of a language _express_ propositions. Thus, in natural
|
||
languages, propositions are expressed via declarative sentences: a statement
|
||
that _such and such is the case_. For example, in English: _snow is white_,
|
||
_London is the capital of the United Kingdom_, _John is travelling to Stockholm_
|
||
etcetera. Whilst this is true it is important not to assume that a proposition
|
||
reduces to its expression by a given sentence. There are numerous examples of
|
||
why this assumption proves problematic. For example, _il pleut_ and _it is
|
||
raining_ express the same proposition but do so via different sentences in
|
||
different languages. Similarly the semantically ambiguous English sentence _Two
|
||
cars were reported stolen by the police yesterday_ expresses two possible
|
||
propositions (the police reported the car stolen, the police stole the car) that
|
||
are left underdetermined by the surface grammar of the sentence. For simplicity
|
||
we will talk about propositions exclusively in terms of sentences but it is
|
||
important to note that the two are not straightforwardly interchangeable.
|
||
|
||
Not every sentence in a language has a propositional form. Consider for example
|
||
_Áchtung!_ or _thanks_. It is not obvious that these sentences express a
|
||
proposition in the manner of declarative sentences. Philosophers and linguists
|
||
have called expressions that do not satisfy propositional criteria
|
||
[speech acts](https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Speech_act). The difference between
|
||
declarative sentences and speech acts (like thanking someone or issuing an
|
||
order) centers on the fact that the former possess clear _truth-conditions_ that
|
||
reduce to a given _truth-value_. In the case of _il pleut_ the sentence is true
|
||
if it is raining and false otherwise. Those are its truth-conditions. Its
|
||
truth-value is the particular assignment that is made on the basis of these
|
||
conditions. Assume it is not raining; in this case the truth-value of _il pleut_
|
||
is false.
|
||
|
||
Although declarative sentences are a subset of the totality of possible
|
||
grammatical expressions in any natural language, they are clearly an important
|
||
subset. They form the basis of all scientific and mathematical discourse and are
|
||
our primary means of spreaking and reasoning about the world. The scope of
|
||
propositional logic is limited to sentences that have this declarative property.
|
||
There are no questions, commands or exhortations in propositional logic, only
|
||
statements which may be true or false.<sup>1</sup>
|
||
|
||
The purpose of propositional logic is to analyse propositions in terms of their
|
||
truth conditions and to derive rules governing their proper application and
|
||
combination in arguments. Equipped with these rules, we are able to demonstrate
|
||
for example that an argument is valid or that it displays sound reasoning. On
|
||
the other hand, the same rules will allow us to demonstrate when an argument is
|
||
invalid or that it leads to contradiction.
|
||
|
||
## Arguments and consistency
|
||
|
||
Propositional logic proceeds upon two interconnected axes:
|
||
|
||
<ol>
|
||
<li>Analysing compound propositions in terms of their constituent parts</li>
|
||
<li>Analysing a proposition in relation to other propositions</li>
|
||
</ol>
|
||
|
||
In this post we are focused on the second axis. The first will be covered in a
|
||
future post on logical connectives and truth-tables.
|
||
|
||
When we analyse a series of propositions and the relations between them we call
|
||
the group a _set_. Sets possess logical _properties_. The first such property we
|
||
will define is **consistency**.
|
||
|
||
> A given set of propositions is consistent if and only if it is possible for
|
||
> each member of the set to be true at the same time. It is inconsistent just if
|
||
> this is not the case.
|
||
|
||
The following set of propositions form an inconsistent set.<sup>2</sup> Can you
|
||
spot the inconsistency?
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
(1) Anyone who takes astrology seriously is crazy.
|
||
(2) Jane is my sister and no sister of mine has a crazy person for a husband.
|
||
(3) Richard is Jane's husband and he checks his horoscope every morning.
|
||
(4) Anyone who checks their horoscope takes astrology seriously.
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
The set is inconsistent because it is not the case that all the propositions can
|
||
be true at once. Specifically: if (1), (3), and (4) are true, (2) cannot be.
|
||
Alternatively, if (2), (3) and (4) are true (1) cannot be.
|
||
|
||
Let's illuminate the first instance of inconsistency. On the one hand we assert
|
||
that taking astrology seriously is crazy and we assume that checking your
|
||
horoscope means that you take astrology seriously. Richard is Jane's husband and
|
||
he checks his horoscope each morning. By definition then, Richard is crazy and
|
||
Jane is married to him, but if I believe this, I cannot believe that my sister
|
||
would not marry a crazy person. My beliefs are inconsistent.
|
||
|
||
Now, the second instance of inconsistency. Jane, my sister, is married to
|
||
Richard. None of my sisters have a crazy husband. Richard checks his horoscope
|
||
each day and therefore takes astrology seriously. If this is the case, I cannot
|
||
believe that taking astrology seriously is crazy because otherwise my sister
|
||
cannot be married to Richard.
|
||
|
||
In deconstructing the inconsistencies in the scenario of Richard and Jane we
|
||
have been concerned to point out that one proposition _implies_ or _follows_
|
||
another proposition. Intuitively we have been invoking the logical notion of an
|
||
**argument**. This is not so different from what we mean by an argument in
|
||
ordinary life. If we are arguing with someone, we believe that they are wrong
|
||
about something where 'something' is a proposition and 'wrong' means _false_.
|
||
For example _the prime minister is a liar_. A more logical way to put this is
|
||
that we believe their beliefs about a set of propositions are inconsistent. In
|
||
order to make assertions about the relative consistency or inconsistency of a
|
||
set of propositions we advance arguments. This is like seeking to change the
|
||
person's viewpoint by showing that their belief _A_ conflicts with their other
|
||
belief _B_ or that if _A_ is true, they cannot believe _B_.
|
||
|
||
In the example above each proposition in the set has equal footing; we have not
|
||
distinguished one type of proposition from any other. When we construct an
|
||
argument however, we distinguish the propositions by type. We say that one or
|
||
more propositions are _premises_ and one proposition is the _conclusion_:
|
||
|
||
> An argument is a set of propositions comprising one or more premises and a
|
||
> conclusion. The conclusion is taken to be supported by the premises.
|
||
|
||
Let's demonstrate how this works by making an implicit argument from previous
|
||
example explicit:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
(P1) Anyone who checks their horoscope takes astrology seriously.
|
||
(P2) Richard checks his horoscope.
|
||
(C) Richard takes astrology seriously.
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
This constitutes a logical argument because of how the propositions are
|
||
arranged: we are asserting that the conclusion (C) is supported by premises P1
|
||
and P2. We call such arguments **syllogisms**.
|
||
|
||
## Evaluation criteria for arguments
|
||
|
||
In what sense do the premises support the conclusion of an argument? What is the
|
||
relation between these two types of proposition? The word 'support' is rather
|
||
vague. In logic there are different ways to assess the qualility of an argument:
|
||
**inductive strength** and **deductive validity**.
|
||
|
||
Consider the following argument:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
(P1) When a cat scratches itself it can mean it has fleas.
|
||
(P2) Our tabby, Carrot has been scratching himself a lot lately.
|
||
(C) Carrot has fleas.
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
To ask ourselves whether this is a strong argument is to reflect on whether we
|
||
have good grounds for believing the conclusion given the premises. My intuition
|
||
that this is a reasonable argument but not a particularly strong one. It doesn't
|
||
strain credulity but it is by no means watertight.
|
||
|
||
Contrast it with this argument:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
(P1) Every day the sun rises in the east.
|
||
(P2) The sun rose in the east today.
|
||
(C) The sun will rise in the east tomorrow.
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
This strikes me as a stronger argument than the first. If you had to bet on
|
||
Carrot having fleas or the sun rising in the East you would put your money on
|
||
the latter although you would probably get better returns on the former. With
|
||
arguments of this nature we are proceeding on the basis of likelihood. The
|
||
technical term for this is _induction_ : given some background context of
|
||
beliefs (for instance the typical behaviour of cats and the planet) there are
|
||
stronger or weaker grounds for accepting the conclusion of an argument bases on
|
||
its premises.
|
||
|
||
> An argument is inductively strong if and only if the conclusion is probably
|
||
> true given the premises.
|
||
|
||
Although the arguments differ in their relative strength they are both inductive
|
||
arguments. This is because they are each falsifiable. In the first case, this is
|
||
obvious: Carrot might not have fleas and could be scratching for some other
|
||
reason. Perhaps surprisingly, the second argument is also falsifiable. The
|
||
magnetic field of the Earth could switch polarity meaning that while the Earth
|
||
would not change its position relative to the sun, our compass would be inverted
|
||
and therefore indicate that the sun rising in the west. This is very unlikely to
|
||
happen imminently but it _will_ happen at some point in the next 10,000 years.
|
||
Therefore the conclusion could prove false.
|
||
|
||
The next obvious is whether all arguments are like this. Is probability the best
|
||
we can hope for? Fortunately not. Propositional logic is a deductive schema
|
||
which means it aims for truths that are not falsifiable in the manner of the two
|
||
examples above. It is this criterion of evaluation that we mainly interested in
|
||
when we use logic as a formal discipline. This is the domain of deductive
|
||
validity. Validity is our second key logical property.
|
||
|
||
> An argument is deductively valid if and only if it is not possible for the
|
||
> premises to be true and the conclusion false.
|
||
|
||
## Validity and soundness
|
||
|
||
The following syllogism is an example of a valid argument:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
(P1) All fish live in the sea and only in the sea.
|
||
(P2) Cod are fish.
|
||
(C) Cod live in the sea.
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
And here is an invalid argument:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
(P1) All fish live in the sea and only in the sea.
|
||
(P2) Cod are fish.
|
||
(C) Cod live on land.
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
In the valid instance, there is no sense to the idea that we might accept each
|
||
premise and yet deny the conclusion. In the invalid instance this is not the
|
||
case: we can accept each premise and deny the conclusion. We can relate this
|
||
back to the the notion of consistency. Recall that a set of propositions is
|
||
consistent if and only if it is possible for each member to be true at once.
|
||
With the first argument we cannot consistently accept the premises and deny the
|
||
conclusion whereas in the case of the second argument we can quite consistently
|
||
accept the premises and deny the conclusion since the propositions do not
|
||
comprise a consistent set.
|
||
|
||
In contrast to the previous inductive arguments, with valid arguments the
|
||
conclusion is supported purely in virtue of the terms used in the premises and
|
||
the propositions they express. In order to assess the validity of an argument
|
||
like the first it is not neccessary to aquaint oneself with cod and to study
|
||
their behaviour so as to determine whether they do in fact live in the sea. All
|
||
that is necessary is to understand the propositions expressed. Philosophers
|
||
refer to statements of this sort as _analytic_. They are true or false 'by
|
||
definition'. More specifically: the concept of the predicate is contained within
|
||
the concept of the subject for example _all brothers are male_. In the case of
|
||
the argument, we have defined at (P1) that fish are creatures that live in the
|
||
sea so given this definition, the conclusion is bound to follow from the
|
||
premises since it is just a specific instance of the general property already
|
||
defined. Validity is therefore an entirely formal notion that exists over and
|
||
above any facts of the matter. If I have defined 'fish' universally as
|
||
sea-dwellers I cannot without inconsistency say that they are not sea-dwellers.
|
||
|
||
This is further exemplified with an argument like the following:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
(P1) Manchester is the capital of the UK.
|
||
(P2) Manchester is north of Birmingham.
|
||
(C) The capital of the UK is north of Birmingham.
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
Is this a valid argument? To answer this question remember that invalidity means
|
||
that it is possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. In the
|
||
strict logical sense, this is valid argument since _were_ the premises true, the
|
||
conclusion would also be true. The point is that validity is a function of
|
||
truth-conditions not truth-values. The truth value of the first premise and the
|
||
conclusion in the above argument happen to be false but this does not affect its
|
||
validity. There is no necessity to London being the capital of the UK and not
|
||
Manchester. We can imagine things being otherwise which is to say that we can
|
||
entertain the truth-conditions of the proposition and make judgements in
|
||
accordance with it being true or false quite independently of whether it is in
|
||
actuality true/false.
|
||
|
||
We can take this back to the earlier example of the invalid argument about cod:
|
||
in order to judge the argument invalid it was not necessary for us to look for
|
||
cod that live on land and come back empty. Rather we just had to assume that if
|
||
all fish live in the sea then it must be the case that if something is a fish,
|
||
it is a sea-dweller. We made no commitment to fish actually living in the sea.
|
||
|
||
Does this mean that actual truth does not matter to logic? No, it just means
|
||
that validity as a property is decoupled from truth as a property although we
|
||
cannot of course have a grasp of the notion of validity without possessing a
|
||
prior notion of truth. A proposition being true in fact is a property it may or
|
||
not possess in addition to its membership within a valid sequence of reasoning.
|
||
If an argument is both valid and its premises are true in fact we say that it is
|
||
a **sound** argument. This is a stronger criterion of evaluation than validity
|
||
alone.
|
||
|
||
> An argument is sound if and only if it is deductively valid and all of its
|
||
> premises are true.
|
||
|
||
It follows from this definition of soundness that:
|
||
|
||
- an argument cannot be sound if it is not also valid
|
||
- an argument can be valid without being sound
|
||
- if an argument is sound its conclusion must be true
|
||
|
||
(The last point follows from the fact that soundness means the premises are true
|
||
and validity requires that if the premises are true the conclusion must also be
|
||
true.)
|
||
|
||
We have already seen examples of arguments that are valid but not sound in the
|
||
Manchester example, let's close this section with an example where both premises
|
||
and conclusion are true yet the argument is invalid, demonstrating that truth
|
||
alone is not sufficient for soundness.
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
(P1) London is the capital of the UK.
|
||
(P2) The capital of the UK is in the southern part of the country.
|
||
(P3) Cambridge is not the capital of the United Kingdom
|
||
(C) London is south of Cambridge
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
This argument is deductively invalid because we can consistently assert the
|
||
premises but deny the conclusion. Specifically: there isn't anything about the
|
||
premises that makes the denial of the conclusion inconsistent. From the point of
|
||
view of the premises alone, London could be north of Cambridge whilst still
|
||
being in the southern part of the country.
|
||
|
||
## Logical possibility
|
||
|
||
In distinguishing the properties of logical consistency and validity we have
|
||
been making much tacit use of the notion of _possibility_. This is because when
|
||
we consider the validity of an argument we are assessing truth-conditions and
|
||
this consists in asking ourselves what could or could not be the case: were it
|
||
such that _P_, then it would be the case that _Q_. It is important to understand
|
||
what possibility means in the context of logic and how it differs from what we
|
||
might mean ordinarily when we use the term.
|
||
|
||
It is evident from the case of arguments that are valid but not sound that logic
|
||
operates with a specialised notion of possibility. For example it has to be the
|
||
case that the proposition _Every woman can levitate_ is logically possible since
|
||
the following argument is valid:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
(P1) Ellen is a woman.
|
||
(P2) Every woman can levitate.
|
||
(C) Ellen can levitate.
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
But we know of course that women cannot levitate. When we assert that this is
|
||
impossible we are relying on a stronger notion of possibility than logical
|
||
possibility. It follows that the concept of possibility can have different
|
||
degrees. The scope of the concept of possibility has been the concern of
|
||
logicians and philosophers since at least the time of Plato and numerous
|
||
different formulations exist. The notion that we mostly work with unreflectively
|
||
in everyday life is nomological possibility. This means 'governed by the
|
||
application of laws' where these laws pertain to our current understanding of
|
||
the natural world as determined by physics. Levitation is therefore
|
||
nomologically impossible but logically possible.
|
||
|
||
If logical possibility is not contrained by the laws of physics does it place
|
||
any restrictions on what is possible? Logic applies a single restriction, the
|
||
law of non-contradiction: a proposition cannot both be true and false at once.
|
||
The following propositions are examples of a contradictory propositions.
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
There is a dog that is not a dog.
|
||
Today is Tuesday and today is not Tuesday.
|
||
The cat that is dead is alive.
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
From this we can derive the following property of logical possibility:
|
||
|
||
> A proposition is logically possible just if it does not imply a contradiction.
|
||
|
||
## Logical truth, falsity and indeterminacy
|
||
|
||
What are the truth-conditions of a contradictory proposition? We know that a
|
||
logically possible proposition such as _every woman can levitate_ could be true
|
||
or false. It has to be so because we are capable of constructing valid arguments
|
||
where it features as a premise and a valid argument implies the possible truth
|
||
of its premises.
|
||
|
||
In the case of a contradiction there are no conditions under which it could be
|
||
judged to be true. For this reason, contradictions are classified as **logically
|
||
false**. This is distinct from ordinary falsity where a proposition _could_ be
|
||
true but happens to be false. Logically false propositions are universally false
|
||
and could never be true. This is consistent with our previous observation of the
|
||
law of non-contradiction: if a proposition cannot be both true and false at once
|
||
we are saying that something _cannot be the case_ which is of course to say _is
|
||
false_.
|
||
|
||
Logical falsity is therefore another property that a proposition may possess and
|
||
it is a property that is possessed by all propositions that are contradictions:
|
||
|
||
> A proposition is logically false if and only if it is not possible for the
|
||
> sentence to be true.
|
||
|
||
Complementing logical falsity is **logical truth**:
|
||
|
||
> A proposition is logically true if and only if it is not possible for the
|
||
> sentence to be false.
|
||
|
||
We call logically true propositions tautologies. Some examples:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
An apple is an apple.
|
||
Today is Tuesday or today is not Tuesday.
|
||
The cat is dead or alive.
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
The properties of logical truth and falsity are alike in their universality.
|
||
Propositions that are logically true do not exclude any possibility (today is
|
||
Tuesday or it is not Tuesday; there is no possible state outside of this)
|
||
whereas logically false propositions exclude all possibilities (there is no
|
||
scenario where today is both Tuesday and not Tuesday).
|
||
|
||
We class all propositions that are not contradictions or tautologies **logically
|
||
indeterminate** propositions. This means that their truth-value is not assigned
|
||
purely on the basis of the meanings of the terms of which they are comprised.
|
||
_It is raining_ for example, is logically indeterminate because we cannot know
|
||
its truth-value just by reflecting on the meaning of the predicate _is raining_.
|
||
It may be true under certain conditions and false under others and in order to
|
||
know the specific truth-value at a given moment, we must look to states of
|
||
affairs beyond the sentence. The vast majority of propositions expressed in
|
||
natural and formal languages are indeterminate in this manner.
|
||
|
||
## Summary
|
||
|
||
In this post we introduced propositions as descriptions of states of affairs
|
||
that possess truth-conditions. We noted that propositions are expressed in
|
||
language through the medium of declarative sentences and that not every
|
||
expression in a language possesses a propositional form. Two key properties that
|
||
pertain to sets of propositions were introduced and exemplified: consistency and
|
||
validity. In addition we considered different evaluative criteria for logical
|
||
arguments comparing inductive strength with deductive validity. We distinguished
|
||
logical possibility from nomological possibility and explained how the law of
|
||
non-contradiction places bounds on what is logically possible. Equipped with the
|
||
concept of logical possibility we were able to introduce logical truth and
|
||
falsity, analysing the truth-conditional form of tautologies and contradictions
|
||
and noting that propositions that are neither logically true or false are
|
||
logically indeterminate.
|
||
|
||
## Notes
|
||
|
||
<ol>
|
||
<li>These all being standard instances of speech acts which are resistant to truth-conditional analyses as noted above.</li>
|
||
<li>This example comes from (Bergmann, Moor and Nelson, 2014).</li>
|
||
</ol>
|
||
|
||
## References
|
||
|
||
Bergmann, M., Moor, J. and Nelson, J. (2014). The logic book. Boston:
|
||
Mcgraw-Hill/Connect Learn Succeed.
|
||
|
||
Wikipedia Contributors (2019). Speech-act. [online] Wikipedia. Available at:
|
||
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Speech_act.
|
||
|
||
|