Propositions generated from other (simple) propositions by means of propositional connectives are [compound propositions](/Logic/Propositional_logic/Atomic_and_molecular_propositions.md).
We know that [logically determinant](/Logic/General_concepts/Logical_indeterminacy.md) propositions express a truth value. When simple propositions are joined with a connective to make a compound proposition they also have a truth value. This is determined by the nature of the connective and the truth value of the constituent propositions. We therefore call connectives of this nature truth _functional_ connectives since the **truth value of the compound is a function of the truth values of its components**.
> A propositional connective is used truth-functionally if and only if it is used to generate a compound proposition from one or more propositions in such a way that the truth value of the generated compound is wholly determined by the truth-values of those one or more propositions from which the compound is generated, no matter what the truth values may be.
Each truth-functional connective has a characteristic **truth table**. This discloses the conditions under which the constituent propositions have a given truth value when combined with one or more connectives.
A molecular proposition joining two disjuncts P and Q is true if either disjunct is true or if both disjuncts are true and false otherwise. This corresponds to the inclusive sense of OR in natural language.
In contrast to the two previous connectives, negation is a unary connective not a binary connective. We use `~` to symbolise negation. It does not join two or more propositions, it applies to one proposition as a whole. This can be a simple proposition or a complex proposition. It simply negates the truth-value of whichever proposition it is applied to. Hence applied to P, it is true if P is false. And if P is false, it is true when P is true. !
The material conditional approximates the meaning expressed in natural language when we say _if_ such-and-such is the case _then_ such-and-such will the case. Another way of expressing the sense of the material conditional is to say that **P** implies **Q.**
We call the proposition that expresses the 'if' proposition the **antecedent** and the proposition that expresses the 'then' statement the **consequent**. The symbol we use to represent the material conditional is `⊃` although you may see `→` used as well.
The material conditional is perhaps the least intuitive of the logical connectives. The first case (TT) closely matches what we expect the connective to mean: it has rained so the pavement is wet. The antecedent is true and therefore the consequent is true. This chimes with what we tend to mean by 'if' in natural language. In the second case (TF) it also makes sense: the complex proposition is false because it rained and the pavement wasn't wet: this negates the truth of the expression. The final case (FF) is also straight forward. It didn't rain therefore the pavement wasn't wet, thus the overall assertion that rain implies wet pavements is retained.
To some degree one just has to take these statements as axioms, whether or not they have intuitive sense is a secondary, more philosophical question. The semantic issues arise because we tacitly assume the material conditional to be a causal connective: there is something about the nature of **P** that _engenders_ or _brings about_**Q** but causality is not a logical concern.
If we instead just focus on the simple propositions that comprise the truth value it is more plausible. In the case of FT we can say it didn't rain yet the pavement was wet does not stop the pavement being wet when it rains. The fact that I can pour a beer on the pavement thereby making it wet doesn't stop or render false the idea that the rain can also make the pavement wet. The same explanation covers the FF case: it hasn't rained and so the pavement is not wet does not contradict the assertion that when it rains the pavement will be wet.
A disjunction is true whenever either disjunct is true so when both are false the overall expression is false, the same as with FT and FF with the material conditional.
The material biconditional equates to the English expression 'if and only if', as a conditional connective it therefore avoids some of the perplexity aroused by its material cousin. In this scenario both antecedent and consequent have to be true for the overall expression to be true. If either is false the complex proposition is false. Other ways of expressing the semantics of this connective is to say that one proposition implies the other or that **P** and **Q** are equivalent.
There is no possibility in which James passes the exam and has not studied every day. If he studies for three out of the seven days leading up to the exam he will not pass. Alternatively, there is no possibility that James studied every day yet failed the exam. The antecedent and consequent are locked, as indicated by the truth-table:
The last condition (FF) maybe requires some explanation: if he has not studied every day then he cannot have passed the exam. Therefore, to say that he will pass iff he studies every day is rendered true.
So far we have applied connectives to simple propositions. In so doing we generate complex propositions. However propositions and connectives are inherently generative: we can build more complex expressions from less complex parts, using more than one type of connective or several different connectives to make larger complex propositions and express more detailed logical conditions ans statements about the world.
At the highest level of generality the proposition is a conjunction with two disjuncts: `P v Q` and `~R` . Therefore, for the proposition to be true both conjuncts must be true. The first conjunct is true just if one of the subordinate disjuncts is true (Socrates is either a philosopher, a drinker, or both). The second conjunct is true just if Socrates is not a politician. Thus there is only one variation for the second conjunct (not being a politician) and two variations for the first conjunct (being a drinker/being a philosopher) hence there are three cases where the overall proposition is true.
Once we start working with complex propositions with more than one truth-functional connective it becomes clear that the same proposition expressed in natural language can be expressed formally more than one way and thus that in logical terms, both formal expressions are equivalent. We can prove this equivalence by comparing truth tables.
The example above is a key equivalence that you will encounter a lot especially when deriving formal proofs. It goes together with another one. We have noted them both below for future reference:
This would not be a well-formed proposition because at most truth functional connectives can only connect two simple propositions. It would not be possible to generate truth conditions for this proposition in its current form. Instead we introduce brackets to enforce a binary grouping of simple propositions. In this instance, the placement of the brackets does not affect the accurate interpretation of the truth conditions of the compound, so the following two formalisations are equivalent: